More on English Preposition Stranding
1 IntroductionAs mentioned in the introductory notes to Postal's (1997) book, Langendoen and Pullum (henceforth L&P) published in a 1977 CLS book of squibs a short presentation of various puzzles relating to instances of stranded (as opposed to pied piped) Ps in what are mostly double object constructions of some sort. We will aim here to recall some of the data from that 1977 squib, and to suggest that the prohibition on P stranding noted by L&P might be viewed as part of a more general prohibition on extraction from specifier positions. That it is possible now to consider this approachwhich we sketch below in only a very nascent formis a result of the consequences for movement posed by recent developments in the theory of internal VP structure, and by other current phrase structural conceptions. Thus, although the generalization suggested here is not conclusive by any means, it does suggest a line of inquiry that might not have been possible twenty years ago. 2 The L&P DataWe wish to focus mainly upon those sentences presented in L&P's examples (24). In these examples, an NP extracted from a PP without pied piping of the P results in ungrammaticality; this appears to occur specifically when the PP at issue immediately follows the V to which it serves as complement, with a second complement to the V appearing to the immediate right of the PP. The observed ungrammaticality appears to occur in all standard A-bar extraction types, including wh-questions, relative clauses, and topicalization structures. We include the relevant wh-question examples here; all sentences not designated with an L&P example number are own additions:
NP extraction stranding the same P is fully licit when the PP position with respect to the other complement of V is reversed:
In fact, the marked PP position displayed in (12) appears to be quite degraded even in examples without co-occurring extraction and P stranding:
However, the cause of the degradation in (56) cannot be the sole cause of the ungrammaticality in (12): not only are judgements for the examples with P stranding more strongly ungrammatical than for those without it, but the former improve significantly when the complement of V which appears at the right edge of the sentence is made heavier, while the latter do not:
Furthermore, the sort of ungrammaticality present in the cases of extraction in (12) appears to occur even when the relevant PP occupies a position which is fully licit without NP extraction which strands the P. Thus, the ungrammaticality of (1113) seems on a par with that of (12):
As was true for (12), (1113) become gramamtical when the PP in which P stranding occurs is the linearly second complement to follow the V, as shown in the (a) examples of (1416). However, contrasting with the ungrammaticality of (56), the PP position from which extraction is ungrammatical in (1113) is licit when P stranding does not take place. This latter point is shown in the (b) examples of (1416).
In contrast to these patterns, PP complements of talk appear grammatical with P stranding, regardless of whether the stranded P occurs immediately following the V, or separated from the V by an additional argument:
L&P also show that, where such extraposition structures are possible, the presence of expletive it immediately following the V in examples such as (15) produces contrastingly full grammaticality:
To add to this empirical picture, and as a segue to the next section, we note additionally that extraction out of a CP which immediately follows the V of a double object construction appears to be as unacceptable for these Vs as was extraction out of the PP:
We can thus note so far that, with the exception of the V talk, the patterns in the traits of the English examples seen so far have all been consistent with a generalization that extraction of an element out of the position to the immediate linear right of the main V and preceding a second verbal complement appears to result consistently in ungrammaticality. Extraction of the entire complement in this positionin contrast to extraction of just a subpart of this elementappears to be licit:1
3 Additional Data and Theoretical ImplicationsIn this section, we suggest a possible direction that an account of the facts discussed above might take. The considerations in this section are quite tentative, and are not intended to address all of the facts at this point. The first observation that we would like to make is that there could be a connection between the ungrammatical extractions in (12), (913), and (2223), and the classic CED effects illustrated in (28):
On this view, the contrast in (28) and the contrasts observed above might both arise from a sensitivity to phrase structure position in terms of the acceptability of extraction. More concretely, the grammaticality contrast shown in (28ab) and the contrasts just shown in Section 2 could both be attributed to whether or not the XP from which extraction has taken place is a specifier position or a complement position. Traditional analyses of (28a-b) have made crucial mention of the complement vs. specifier status of the NP from which extraction has taken place. Chomsky (1986), for example, distinguishes between the specifier position in (28b), from which extraction is ungrammatical, and the complement position in (28a), from which extraction is licit, by the notion of L-marking. Thus, [Spec, IP] is a non-L-marked position, whereas a verbal complement is L-marked by the V; extraction is therefore much worse in (28b) than in (28a). Extending this kind of analysis to the cases documented in the previous section would be arduous and ultimately unenlightening, because even if we could determine which relevant syntactic elements were L-markers and which were not, we would then have only a list, but no clear generalization. A more general account might involve claiming (with admitted brute force) that extraction from an XP in a specifier position is ruled out, while extraction out of a complement position is acceptable. This kind of generalization would hold irrespective of category or A- versus A-bar distinctions. Let us consider the examples from Section 2 with the hypothesis just discussed in mind. If the V mention in (12) and (22) is a double object verb on a par with Vs like put or give, then we could follow approaches taken in some recent work (see e.g. Johnson 1991, McCloskey 2000) and assign to these sentences the structures shown in (29ab). (We abstract away from V movement here.)
Consider in this light a sentence like (30), another case of ungrammatical P stranding observed by L&P:
The bracketed PP plausibly occupies [Spec, IP] position (see e.g. Bresnan 1994), as follows:
In these examples, then, it seems that extraction from out of an element in specifier position results in ungrammaticality. This occurs with extraction from [Spec, VP] in (29), and from [Spec, IP] in (31) and in the CED example in (28b). Consider now examples (32ab). (32a) is based on L&P's (6), and (32b) is based on a classic example of Paul Postal, used as an argument against successive cyclicity:
In each of these sentences, the PP from which extraction has taken place is likely best analyzed as being in [Spec, CP] position:
We again have extraction from a specifier position which proves to be illicit. As a final example, let us consider (910) from Section 2, which involve Heavy XP Shift (HXPS). Putting aside for now many issues which arise here, HXPS is often assumed to involve a rightward movement of the heavy XP. However, others propose radically different analyses. For example, Kayne (1994) and Shlonsky and Belletti (1995) both assume that this linear order is in fact derived via leftward movement of the non-heavy XP to a specifier position which c-commands the heavy XP, with the latter not undergoing any rightward movement. If these analyses are on the right track, then they assign structures to instances of HXPS which are again consistent with the generalization being considered here. Important details aside, the structures to consider, then, would be as in (34ab):
If the structures for these ungrammatical extractions are indeed as shown in (29), (31), and (3334), then we have come close to a generalization that accounts for the facts discussed here in a uniform fashion. Note that, at present, this generalization only concerns extraction out of an XP in a specifier position, but, as consistent with the grammaticality of extraction with pied piping in (2627), would not apply to full extraction of a specifier XP. Although more research is clearly needed on our part to find independent motivation for the structures above, we wish at this point to point out simply that they are plausible. 4 SpecifiersIf the considerations above are on the right track, then the question to ask is what is responsible for causing extraction out of an XP in a specifier position to be impossible. Recent proposals by Kayne (1994), and related proposals by Uriagereka (1999) and Nunes and Uriagereka (2000, henceforth N&U) provide a way to answer this question. Kayne suggests, based on his Linear Correspondence Axiom (LCA), that no linear ordering can be determined between the specifier to a head, the head itself, and the complements of the head. He thus proposes that the relation of specifier be reanalyzed as a case of adjunction, thereby guaranteeing satisfaction of the LCA. If all specifiers were to be reanalyzed as adjuncts, then the ungrammaticality of extracting from an XP in specifier position suggested here might plausibly follow as part of something like the Adjunct Island Condition (see Chomsky 1986 and others). N&U (2000) also assume LCA and propose relatedly that specifiers to a head cannot be linearized with the head or its complements. Instead of entailing that specifiers be reanalyzed as adjuncts in order to satisfy the LCA, however, N&U propose as an alternative that all specifiers (and adjuncts) in a syntactic structure must be "Spelled-Out" (i.e. sent to the PF component) separately from the other elements in that structure (namely those which represent the head-complement relation). Under their approach, the separate Spelling-Out of the specifier means essentially that no syntactic operationsincluding movement and deletionmay access its internal parts. Their proposal is developed to account for the CED contrast in (28ab), but has not, as far as we are aware, been considered, as suggested here, as a possible explanation for the L&P-type examples presented above. Both the Kayne and N&U proposals provide a plausible "deeper explanation" for the generalization being considered here to account for the facts laid out above. Further study is again necessary to determine whether this is an appropriate line of research, and, if so, whether the proposal by Kayne or that by N&U is best suited to handle these facts. We end this squib, however, with two additional pieces of the puzzle. 5 Some Final ConsiderationsTwo additional and interesting aspects of the N&U system are perhaps worth mentioning. N&U claim that their system developed to account for contrasts like (28ab) can, with a few additional assumptions, be made to accommodate in addition the weakened ungrammaticality of sentences like (28b) when the gap left by extraction is a parasitic gap:
We note, then, that their system might predict as well that the ungrammaticality of the L&P-type examples considered here would also be weakened if the gap left by extraction were a parasitic gap. Our own judgements on such examples are a bit unreliable at this point, and so we leave it to the reader(s) to judge for themselves:
Although we must leave checking of these issues and of the details of N&U's predictions for future research here, any improved acceptability for the examples in (36) would provide an intriguing addition to evidence that the ungrammaticality of CED and L&P-type facts might be connected. A clearer prediction made by the N&U system but again not considered by these authors is that operations like sluicing should be impossible in the contexts of L&P- and CED-type examples. This is because sluicing would involve extraction from the positions where it is supposed to be prohibited, even though that position has subsequently been deleted. Our initial judgements on the relevant examples is that they are in fact acceptableor at least much better than their non-sluiced counterparts. Here again, we will leave it to the readers to provide their own judgements, and leave a more systematic investigation to future work:
If these sentences are grammatical, then they pose a challenge to the proposal developed by N&U. On the other hand, they are perfectly expected under Kayne's analysis (along with whatever other mechanisms are needed to account for the weakening of the extraction violation under deletion). 6 ConclusionTo conclude, the question we leave the reader with is whether or not the constructions discussed in this squib can be given a uniform account in terms of the phrase structural contrast between complement positions and specifier positions. We have also explored briefly ways in which the generalization posed hereif it should turn out to be correctmight be explained in terms of recent proposals about phrase structure and related types of constraints. In addition to the needed checking of the grammaticality judgements and fleshing out of the analysis, deeper questions emerge from this inquiry as well. In particular, why should the assumptions described above need to hold, and, more generally, why should phrase structure pose such conditions on the range of permissible extractions? We hope, however, to have presented enough here to show that this approach is at least interesting and worth thinking about in more explicit terms in the time to come. ReferencesBresnan, Joan (1994) "Locative Inversion and the Architecture of Universal Grammar", Language 70: 73131. Chomsky, Noam (1986) Barriers, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA. Kayne, Richard (1994) The Antisymmetry of Syntax, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA. Johnson, Kyle (1991) "Object Positions", Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 9: 577636. Langendoen, D. Terrence, and Geoffrey K. Pullum (1977) "Preposition Stranding in English: A problem and a mystery", in CLS Book of Squibs/Cumulative Index 19681977, Samuel E. Fox, Woodford A. Beach, and Shulamith Philosoph, eds., pp. 6465, Chicago Linguistic Society, Chicago. Larson (1988) "On the Double Object Construction", Linguistic Inquiry 19.3: 335391. McCloskey, James (2000) "Quantifier Float and Wh-Movement in an Irish English", Linguistic Inquiry 31.1:5784. Nunes, Jairo and Juan Uriagereka (2000) "Cyclicity and Extraction Domains", Syntax 3.1: 2043. Postal, Paul M. (1998) Three Investigations of Extraction, MIT Press, Cambridge. Shlonsky, Ur and Adriana Belletti (1995) "The Order of Verbal Complements: A comparative study", Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 13: 489526. Uriagereka, Juan (1999) "Multiple Spell-out", in Working Minimalism, Samuel Epstein and Norbert Hornstein, eds., pp. 251282, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA. Endnote1 We make the plausible (we think) assumption here that the moved PP originates as the first complement linearly following the V, although it could in principle have originated as the linearly second complement to follow the V. [Back]
|